Issofa Moyouwou 1, Hugues Tchantcho 2, Nicolas Gabriel Andjiga 1
1Department of mathematics, Higher Teachers' Training College, Yaounde, 47, Cameroon
2Department of mathematics, The University of Yaounde I, Yaounde, 812, Cameroon
Correspondence to: Issofa Moyouwou , Department of mathematics, Higher Teachers' Training College, Yaounde, 47, Cameroon.
Email: |  |
Copyright © 2012 Scientific & Academic Publishing. All Rights Reserved.
Abstract
It is well-kown that the (Aumann-Maschler) bargaining set of a transferable utility game (or simply a game) with less than five players coincides with the core of the game, provided that the core is nonempty. We show that this coincidence still holds for a superset of the core, the objection-free core which is the set of all imputations with no bargaining set type objection. Furthermore, for any game and for any coalition structure, the objection-free core contains the core, is a subset of the bargaining set and is a polyhedron when it is nonempty.
Keywords:
Core, Coalition Structure, Bargaining Set, Objection-Free Core
Cite this paper: Issofa Moyouwou , Hugues Tchantcho , Nicolas Gabriel Andjiga , The Core, the Objection-Free Core and the Bargaining Set of Transferable Utility Games, Journal of Game Theory, Vol. 2 No. 2, 2013, pp. 18-22. doi: 10.5923/j.jgt.20130202.03.
1. Introduction
In the literature, there are many solution concepts to the problem of payoff allocation arising from a transferable utility cooperative game (or simply a game) when players are grouped according to a fixed coalition structure; especially core solutions (see[1]) and bargaining set solutions (see[2],[3] or[4]). Given a coalition structure, the core plays a central role and generally is a subset of many other solution concepts. For instance, given a game and any coalition structure, it is well-known that the (standard) bargaining set
as defined in[2] is a superset of the core. Due to its characterization by a unique set of predefined linear inequalities, the core is surely the most tractable solution concept. It is then important to look for ideal situations where the core is equivalent to a given solution concept.It is shown in[5] that when the core of a game with less than five players is nonempty (the game is balanced), it coincides with the bargaining set
. This proves that the bargaining set of a balanced game with less than five players is a polyhedron instead of a union of several possibly non disjoint or empty polyhedra (see[6] for a full description of
). Roughly, the multitude of polyhedra that make up the bargaining set of a balanced game with less than five players collapses in a unique polyhedron, the core.In this paper we prove that the same result holds when we replace the core by the objection-free core which is the set of all imputations with no bargaining set type objection. Moreover, the objection-free core for any coalition structure is a superset of the core, is a unique polyhedron when it is nonempty, is a subset of the bargaining set
and for less than five player games, the objection-free core coincides with
whenever it is nonempty. The remainder of the paper is organized as follows : in the next section devoted to the model, core and bargaining set concepts are presented and the notion of objection-free core is introduced. In section 3, the relationship between the core and the objection-free core is studied as well as the relationship between the objection-free core and the bargaining set. Section 4 concludes the paper.
2. The Model
2.1. The Core and the Bargaining Set 
Consider a nonempty finite set N of n players. Denote by
the set of all partitions of N and by 2N the set of all nonempty subsets of N. Hereafter, a partition N is called a coalition structure and elements of a given coalition structure are called blocs. In order to simplify notations, coalitions will sometimes be written without braces; for example the coalition {i,j} will be denoted by ij, N\{i,j} by N\ij, ...A transferable utility cooperative game is a pair (N,v) where N is the set of players and v is a map, called the coalitional function, from the power set of N into the set
of real numbers such that
For any nonempty subset S of individuals, v(S) is the gain (or the cost if it is negative) obtained by members of S when they are grouped in S.For a coalition structure
two players i and j are partners if i and j belong to the same bloc of
and a payoff allocation is any vector
such that
Given a payoff allocation x and a coalition S, let x(S) =
with
Note that x(S) is the total payoff allocation of the coalition S over the payoff allocation x. The excess of a coalition S over x, is the real number
The excess
measures the dissatisfaction of the coalition S over the payoff allocation x. For a game (N,v) and a coalition structure
, a
-imputation is a payoff allocation
such that
The set of all imputations for the coalition structure
is denoted by
Note that :
Given a coalition structure
, the
-core, denoted by
is the set of all
-imputations x such that,
A profile of balancing weights is any collection
of real numbers such that
A game (N,v) is
-balanced if for any profile of balancing weights 
When individuals form the grand coalition - that is
(or simply the core) is stated in the following Bondareva-Shapley theorem ([7] and[8]).Theorem 1 A necessary and sufficient condition that the core of a game (N,v) is not empty is that the game is {N}-balanced.The Bondareva-Shapley theorem is still valid for any coalition structure
is nonempty if and only if the game is
-balanced. This clearly shows that core imputations may not exist for some games. Bargaining sets are alternative solutions to overcome the possible emptiness of the core. Roughly speaking, bargaining sets select imputations that are stable via a certain bargaining possibilities of the players. In the case of the Aumann-Maschler bargaining set, given a coalition structure
and a couple (i,j) of partners, an objection of i against j over a
-imputation x is any couple (S,y) such that
and
Remark 1 As stated in lemma 2.1 in[6], given two players i and j, an imputation x and a coalition S, there exists an objection of i against j over x using the coalition S if and only if i and j are partners,
A counter-objection of j against the objection (S,y) of i against j over x is any couple (T,z) such that
and
satisfies
and
The Aumann-Maschler bargaining set is the set
of all stable
-imputations in the sense that a
-imputation x is stable if any objection over x has at least a counter-objection. The bargaining set is nonempty for almost all coalition structures as stated in the following theorem (see[9]):Theorem 2 Given any game (N,v) and any coalition structure
, the bargaining set
is nonempty whenever the set of
-imputations is nonempty.Theorem 2 provides the main structural difference between the core and the bargaining set: while only the core of a balanced game is nonempty, the bargaining set given any coalition structure is always nonempty whenever the set of imputations is nonempty.
2.2. Objection-Free Core
Although the nonemptiness of the bargaining set is proved, the remaining difficulty is a simple determination or description of all imputations that belong to the bargaining set. According to the definition, a basic way to obtain a subset of the bargaining set consists in considering only imputations with no objection.Hereafter, given a game (N,v) and a coalition structure
, the set of all
-imputations with no objection denoted by
is called the objection-free
-core. Clearly the objection-free
-core is contained in
for every coalition structure
. Moreover at core imputations there is no objection. As a consequence the
is contained in the objection-free
for every coalition structure
. It is then straightforward that:
.By definition of an objection, a coalition S involved in an objection separates at least a couple of partners. That is there exists two partners i and j such that
We then split 2N into two subsets: (i)
collects all blocs and all coalitions that separate at least a couple of partners; and (ii)
consists of all coalitions other than blocs that do not separate partners. More formally, a coalition
if and only if T is not a bloc and for any couple (i,j) of partners with respect to
It then follows that
with :
With the notation above, it is straightforward from remark 1 that:Proposition 1 For any game (N,v) and for any coalition structure
,
Clearly, the objection-free core is defined by a unique set of linear inequations (and equations); therefore is a polyhedron when it is nonempty.
3. Results
3.1. The Core and the Objection-Free Core
As mentioned above, the core is a subset of the objection-free core. The following example shows that the core and the objection-free core may be distinct sets of imputations.Example 1 Consider the following four-person game (N,v) defined by v(i) = 0 for all
v(S) = 2 if 
v(S) = 3 if
, v(13) = 6 and v(1234) = 7. Let
be the coalition structure. One can easily check that
= 2N \ {24,123,134,1234} and that
= {( 3,0,3,0)}.Moreover any
-imputation satisfies x1 + x3 = 6 and x2 = x4 = 0. Thus x(1234) = 6 < v(1234) = 7 and then
Clearly the objection-free core with respect to
is nonempty while the core is empty.Proposition 2 For any game (N,v) and for any coalition structure
, if
Proof. Suppose that
and consider
To prove that
it is sufficient to prove that
Consider any imputation
then
Now if
for some
Then
In both cases,
and
Proposition 3 Consider a game (N,v) and a coalition structure
then
for some
with
Proof. Suppose that
Then there exists
Since
such that
By proposition 1, it follows that
Therefore
Note that x is a
-imputation. Thus
Proposition 3 shows that the core and the objection-free core are distinct only for non efficient coalition structures for which some blocs may gain more when their members form a unique bloc.Given a game (N,v) and a coalition structure
, define a new game
as follows:
Remark 2 For any game (N,v) and for any coalition structure
In fact by definition,
for all
The equality between the two sets then immediately follows from the definition of a
-imputation in both games.Proposition 4 For any game (N,v) and for any coalition structure
Proof. Consider
and suppose that
Then by remark 2,
First assume that
for some
with
Any two distinct blocs are disjoint and x is a
-imputation. Thus
and
Now assume that
By definition of
Since
it follows from proposition 1 that
. In both cases,
Hence
and
Now assume that
.Since
then
and
Note that payoffs for coalitions in
are inessential for the objection-free core
This mainly justifies the result in proposition 4 since the game
does not depend on
To generalize the notion of balancedness, consider any nonempty subset E of 2N and define a profile of balancing weights over E as any collection
of real numbers such that
and
In particular, any profile of balancing weights over 2N is simply a (standard) profile of balanced weights presented in section 2. Moreover, a game (N,v) is almost
-balanced if
is nonempty.Proposition 5 For any game (N,v) and for any coalition structure
, the game is almost
-balanced if and only if for any profile of balancing weights 
Proof. Suppose that the game (N,v) is almost
-balanced. Let
be a profile of balanced weights over
Pose
is a profile of balanced weights. Since the game is almost
-balanced, by proposition 4 the game
is
-balanced. Therefore,
Since
for all
for any
then
Conversely suppose that for any profile
of balanced weights over
If
and the game (N,v) is balanced. Now suppose that the coalition structure contains at least two blocs. Let
be a profile of balanced weights. Observe that
where for each


This proves that
is a profile of balanced weights over
. by assumption. But
Thus
Thus the game
By proposition 4, the game is almost
-balanced.
3.2. The Bargaining Set and the Objection-Free Core
The game
has the same core with the game (N,v). The two games also share the same bargaining set as shown below.Proposition 6 For any game (N,v) and for any coalition structure
Proof. Suppose that
.Consider any pair {i,j} of partners and any objection (S,y) in the game
of i against j at x. By remark 1,
Note that i and j are partners and
Therefore
and then
. The objection (S,y) of i in the game
is also an objection in the game (N,v) of i against j at x. Since
there exists a counterobjection (T,z) in the game (N,v) of j against (S,y). Since
then
Therefore (T,z) is also a counterobjection of j against the objection (S,y) of i in the game
In the same way, we prove that any imputation
in
This is clearly due to the fact that both games have the same set of objections and counterobjections on
It is known from[5] that for games with less than five players, when the core for any coalition structure is nonempty, it coincides with the bargaining set. Theorem 3 For any game (N,v) with less than five players and for any coalition structure
whenever
The next theorem states that this result can be extended to the objection-free core.Theorem 4 For any game (N,v) with less than five players and for any coalition structure
whenever
Proof. Suppose that
for a game with at most four players. Then by proposition 4, 
Since the game has at most four players,
By proposition 6, 
That is
As mentioned above, the objection-free core is a subset of the bargaining set. It may be a proper subset of the bargaining set as it is the case with the following example brought to our attention by Solymosi.Example 2 Let N = {1,2,3,4,5} and consider the game (N,v) defined as follows: v(S) = 5 if
v(S) = 6 if | S | = 4, v(S) = 10 if S = N and v(S) = 0 otherwise. For the grand coalition, that is when
= {N}, one can check that x = (2,2,2,2,2) belongs to the core (which then coincides with the objection-free core) and that (5,5,0,0,0) belongs to the bargaining set; but is not a core imputation.
3.3. The Core and the Bargaining Set
Let (N,v) be a game and
be a coalition structure. Given a collection
of real numbers, define the game
as follows:
Note that the game
by increasing (or decreasing) only the share of some blocs.We prove that when each
is sufficiently large, the core and the bargaining set for the game
coincide. This shows that the coincidence of the core and the bargaining set of a game depends on the adequacy of goods available in blocs to yield any bargaining set imputation without any positive excess.Proposition 7 Consider a game (N,v), a coalition structure
of real numbers. Assume that
If for each
and for any
 | (1) |
then
Proof. Assume that
satisfies (1). For
in (1),
for each
Writing this inequality for each
and summing together right-hand terms, we deduce that
By dividing both terms of the latter inequality by
we deduce that
Since
for each
Consider any imputation
Suppose that
Note that
is a
Consider any player
such that
Denote by j a player in
.Then for all
Thus
Hence
Suppose that
Then
Since x is an imputation, for each
Then
By assumption on
Therefore
A contradiction arises.Therefore
and (S,y) is an objection of i against j over x where
Then there exists a counter-objection (T,z) against the objection (S,y) of i against j over x. By definition of a counter-objection,
Then
by definition of j,
As shown for
one can easily check that
and a contradiction arises. Therefore there exists no counter-objection to (S,y).We have shown that if
, then there exists a justified objection of a player against a patner over x. This is clearly a contradiction since
. In conclusion,
Therefore
and then
Proposition 8 Consider a game (N,v) with at most four players and a coalition structure
If
for all collection
of real numbers such that
Proof. Suppose that (N,v) is a game with at most four players and let
be a coalition structure such that
Now consider any collection
of real numbers such that
Since
by theorem 2. But
Consider any imputation
as follows:
Note that
Thus
Moreover, for any coalition S that is not a bloc,
and
This proves that
Recall that there are at most four players. Since
we conclude by theorem 3 that
4. Conclusions
Theorem 4 is an improvement of an earlier result due to[5]. It enlarges the family of games with a tractable bargaining set. The core is nonempty only for some efficient coalition structures for which the game is balanced. Our result is still valid for some non efficient coalition structures and it is equivalent to Solymosi's result for efficient coalition. Moreover, we show that the core and the bargaining set coincide as soon as we sufficiently enlarge the gain of blocs.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
We wish to thank Tamás Solymosi for providing us very illustrative examples.
References
[1] | Gillies D. B. (1959), Solutions to general non-zero-sum games. In: Tucker AW, Luce RD (eds) Contributions to the theory of games IV. Volume 40 of Annals of mathematical studies. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 47–85. |
[2] | Aumann R. J., Maschler M. (1964), The bargaining set for cooperative games. In: Dresher M, Shapley LS, Tucker AW (eds.) Advances in Game Theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton, 443–476. |
[3] | Sudhölter P., Potters J. A. M., (2001), The semireactive bargaining set of a cooperative game. International Journal of Game Theory 30, 117–139. |
[4] | Zhou L. (1994), A new bargaining set of an n-person game and endogenous coalition formation. Games and Economic Behavior 6, 512–526. |
[5] | Solymosi T. (2002), The bargaining set of four-person balanced games. International Journal of Game Theory 31, 1–11. |
[6] | Maschler M. (1966), The inequalities that determine the bargaining set . Israel Journal of Mathematics 4, 127–134. |
[7] | Bondareva O. N. (1963), Some applications of linear programming methods to the theory of cooperative games. Problemi Kibernitiki 10, 119–139. |
[8] | Shapley L. S. (1953), A value for n-person games. Annals of Mathematics Studies 28, 307–318. |
[9] | Peleg B. (1967), Existence theorem for the bargaining set . In: Shubik M (ed.) Essays in Mathematical Economics in Honour of Oskar Morgenstern. Princeton University Press, Princeton, 53–56. |